We now move to a logic that is much more expressive than FO. In the previous "Favorite Logic" posts, I have talked about the gory details of FO. Now, rather than babble about the current logic under consideration, I shall just sample some results that are particularly interesting from my point of view. The readers that happen to be "inspired" by this post are welcome to send me an email for further results or references.
Monadic second-order logic (MSO) is a natural extension of first-order logic with quantifiers over sets of elements in the universe. More precisely, if σ is a vocabulary, MSO sentences ψ over σ are of the form
ψ := Q1X1...QmXm φ
where Qi ∈ {∃,∀}, Xi is a second-order variable, and φ is an FO sentence over σ ∪ {Xi: 1 ≤ i ≤ m}. So, that's the syntax. I will define the semantics by means of an example, the reader should be able to generalize easily.
Suppose σ = {E} is just a vocabulary with one binary relation symbol. We wish to express 2-colorability, i.e., the property
2COL = { G : G is a 2-colorable graph }
It can be proved that 2COL is inexpressible in FO. But, is it expressible in MSO? Positive.
∃ X ∃ Y( (X and Y partitions the vertex-set) and (any two adjacent vertices cannot both belong to X or Y) )
Suppose we are given a graph G = (V,E). Then, we can evaluate this formula as follows: this formula is true in G iff there exist unary relations (i.e. sets) X and Y over G (i.e. X, Y ⊆ V) such that the body of this formula evaluates to true in the structure (V,E,X,Y) (i.e. iff G is 2-colorable). In this case, we intend X and Y to correspond to the two color classes that partition the vertex-set.
The first conjunct above can be expressed by the FO sentence ∀x( X(x) <-> Y(x) ). As an exercise, the reader might enjoy coming up with an FO formula that expresses the second conjunct.
In fact, we can use the same trick to express k-colorability in MSO. Hence, we can immediately conclude that model-checking for MSO is NP-hard when only the models are part of the input (i.e. data-complexity is NP-hard). In fact, since MSO sentences are closed under negation, we also conclude that non-k-colorability is in MSO and therefore model-checking is coNP-hard as well.
Let's conclude this post with a beatiful result that connects MSO to formal language theory. The proof of the result can be found in Straubing's monograph
Finite Automata, Formal Logic, and Circuit Complexity
[Incidentally, David Molnar had a nice post that explores the connection between Straubing's result on "simulating monoids" and homomorphic cryptosystems. So, I thought it would be nice to mention a result from his book, although it was originally proven by Buchi in 1960s.] Roughly speaking, the result says:
A language (a set of strings) L is regular iff L is MSO-definable
What does it mean for a language to be MSO-definable? For notational convenience, let's restrict ourselves to the alphabet {0,1}. First, a binary string s = s0...sn-1 can be considered as a logical structure
S(s) := ({0,...,n-1}; <, U)
whose universe is {0,...,n-1} encoding the "positions" of the string, < is interpreted as the usual linear ordering over such universe, and U is a unary relation with the interpretation that i ∈ U iff si=1. So, if S(s) is a logical encoding of a string s and φ is a formula over the vocabulary {<,U}, the notion of 'S(s) |= φ' makes sense. The language defined by φ, then, is
{ s ∈ {0,1}* : S(s) |= φ }
Buchi's result says that MSO-definable languages are precisely regular languages. Doner, Thatcher, and Wright extended this result to trees:
A set of trees is regular iff it is definable in MSO.
These days, this result is widely employed in the area of "Foundations of XML", which have put automata, logic, and complexity theory under the same roof, which is no short of wondrous. If this interests you, take a loot at some surveys in here.